Art as an Evolutionary Fitness Indicator
To be reliable, fitness indicators must be difficult for low-fitness individuals to produce. Applied to human art, this suggests that beauty equals difficulty and high cost. We find attractive those things that could have been produced only by people with attractive, high-fitness qualities such as health, energy, endurance, hand-eye coordination, fine motor control, intelligence, creativity, access to rare materials, the ability to learn difficult skills, and lots of free time. Also, like bowerbirds, Pleistocene artists must have been physically strong enough to defend their delicate creations against theft and vandalism by sexual rivals.
The beauty of a work of art reveals the artist's virtuosity. This is a very old-fashioned view of aesthetics, but that does not make it wrong. Throughout most of human history, the perceived beauty of an object has depended very much on its cost. That cost could be measured in time, energy, skill, or money. Objects that were cheap and easy to produce were almost never considered beautiful. As Veblen pointed out in The Theory of the Leisure Class, "The marks of expensiveness come to be accepted as beautiful features of the expensive articles." Our sense of beauty was shaped by evolution to embody an awareness of what is difficult as opposed to easy, rare as opposed to common, costly as opposed to cheap, skillful as opposed to talentless, and fit as opposed to unfit.
In her books on the evolution of art, Ellen Dissanayake pointed out that the human arts depend on "making things special" to set them apart from ordinary, utilitarian functions. Making things special can be done in many ways: using special materials, special forms, special decorations, special sizes, special colors, or special styles. Indicator theory suggests that making things special means making them hard to do, so that they reveal something special about the maker. This explains why almost any object can be made aesthetically: anything can be made with special care that would be difficult to imitate by one who was not so careful. From an evolutionary point of view, the fundamental challenge facing artists is to demonstrate their fitness by making something that lower-fitness competitors could not make, thus proving themselves more socially and sexually attractive. This challenge arises not only in the visual arts, but also in music, storytelling, humor, and many other behaviors discussed throughout this book. The principles of fitness-display are similar across different display domains, and this is why so many aesthetic principles are similar.
Anthropologist Franz Boas insisted that in most cultures he studied, the artist's virtuosity was fundamental to artistic beauty. In Primitive Art, he observed that "The enjoyment of form may have an elevating effect upon the mind, but this is not its primary effect. Its source is in part the pleasure of the virtuoso who overcomes technical difficulties that baffle his cleverness." For Boas, works of art, were principally indicators of skill, valued as such in almost every culture. He added, "Among primitive peoples . . . goodness and beauty are the same." Whatever people make, they tend to ornament. He spent a good deal of Primitive Art trying to show that most of the aesthetic preferences of tribal peoples can be traced to the appreciation of patience, careful execution, and technical perfection. In his view, this thirst for virtuosity explains our preferences for regular form, symmetry, perfectly repeated decorative motifs, smooth surfaces, and uniform color fields. Art historian Ernst Gombrich made powerful arguments along similar lines in his book The Sense of Order, which viewed the decorative arts as displays of skill that play upon our perceptual biases.
Beauty conveys truth, but not the way we thought. Aesthetic significance does not deliver truth about the human condition in general: it delivers truth about the condition of a particular human, the artist. The aesthetic features of art make sense mainly as displays of the artist's skill and creativity, not as vehicles of transcendental enlightenment, religious inspiration, social commentary, psycho-analytic revelation, or political revolution. Plato and Hegel derogated art for failing to deliver the same sort of truth that they thought philosophy could produce. They misunderstood the point of art. It is unfair to expect a medium that evolved to display biological fitness to be well adapted for communicating abstract philosophical truths.
This fitness indicator theory helps us to understand why "art" is an honorific term that connotes superiority, exclusive- ness, and high achievement. When mathematicians talk about the "art" of theorem-proving, they are recognizing that good theorems are often beautiful theorems, and beautiful theorems are often the products of minds with high fitness. It is a claim for the social and sexual status of their favorite display medium. Likewise for the "arts" of warfare, chess, football, cooking, gardening, teaching, and sex itself. In each case, art implies that application of skill beyond the pragmatically necessary. Anyone who wishes to imply superiority in their particular line of work is apt to style themselves an artist. The imperatives of fitness display allow us to understand the passion with which people debate whether something is or is not an art. A claim that one's work is art is a claim for sexual and social status.
[...]
This fitness display theory of aesthetics works much better for folk aesthetics than for elite aesthetics. Folk aesthetics concerns what ordinary people find beautiful; elite aesthetics concerns the objects of art that highly educated, rich elites learn are considered worthy of comment by their peers. With folk aesthetics, the focus is on the art-object as a display of the creator's craft. With elite aesthetics, the focus is on the viewer's response as a social display. In response to a landscape painting, folks might say "Well, it's a pretty good picture of a cow, but it's a little smudgy," while elites might say, "How lovely to see Constable's ardent brushwork challenging the anodyne banality of the pastoral genre." The first response seems a natural expression of typical human aesthetic tastes concerning other people's artistic displays, and the second seems more of a verbal display in its own right.
Notes:
The artwork must connect to the potential mate and communicate the fitness of the artist, but it cannot be too errudite, or it becomes elite art and the communication becomes noise.
Folksonomies: culture art evolutionary theory sexual selection
Taxonomies:
/health and fitness (0.621185)
/society/crime/personal offense/assault (0.352217)
/society (0.323288)
Keywords:
art (0.919105 (positive:0.017903)), folk aesthetics (0.767637 (positive:0.256503)), elite aesthetics (0.760946 (positive:0.622921)), Evolutionary Fitness Indicator (0.738972 (positive:0.652285)), Art historian Ernst (0.720028 (positive:0.636678)), Primitive Art (0.719171 (negative:-0.543768)), fine motor control (0.716544 (positive:0.329660)), fitness display theory (0.716096 (positive:0.863269)), different display domains (0.703063 (neutral:0.000000)), Anthropologist Franz Boas (0.690594 (neutral:0.000000)), favorite display medium (0.684460 (positive:0.523263)), uniform color fields (0.681107 (positive:0.420840)), human art (0.678765 (positive:0.459643)), pretty good picture (0.675532 (positive:0.447900)), abstract philosophical truths (0.672530 (positive:0.304945)), elite art (0.670824 (neutral:0.000000)), beautiful theorems (0.667837 (positive:0.561650)), beauty (0.648613 (positive:0.593390)), special care (0.635341 (negative:-0.264070)), fitness indicators (0.635212 (neutral:0.000000)), special forms (0.632336 (positive:0.400779)), special colors (0.632224 (positive:0.450469)), special styles (0.632175 (neutral:0.000000)), special materials (0.631301 (positive:0.462169)), special decorations (0.628714 (positive:0.539971)), special sizes (0.626301 (positive:0.506035)), special means (0.626256 (neutral:0.000000)), artist (0.625345 (positive:0.670047)), difficult skills (0.624626 (neutral:0.000000)), human arts (0.620310 (positive:0.398920))
Entities:
Primitive Art:Facility (0.984039 (negative:-0.543768)), Evolutionary Fitness Indicator:PrintMedia (0.806872 (positive:0.652285)), Franz Boas:Person (0.574548 (neutral:0.000000)), Ellen Dissanayake:Person (0.569994 (positive:0.398920)), Ernst Gombrich:Person (0.545675 (positive:0.636678)), theft:Crime (0.525139 (negative:-0.539791)), Plato:Person (0.513128 (negative:-0.512256)), Veblen:Person (0.511322 (positive:0.385136)), Leisure Class:Organization (0.502329 (positive:0.385136)), vandalism:Crime (0.499777 (negative:-0.539791)), Constable:Person (0.494970 (positive:0.647763))
Concepts:
Aesthetics (0.964095): dbpedia | freebase
Art (0.756298): dbpedia | freebase
Evolution (0.645297): dbpedia | freebase | opencyc
Fitness (0.583947): dbpedia | freebase
Natural selection (0.574932): dbpedia | freebase